Philosophy of Education Essay Example
Philosophy of Education Essay Example

Philosophy of Education Essay Example

Available Only on StudyHippo
  • Pages: 15 (3876 words)
  • Published: November 7, 2017
  • Type: Essay
View Entire Sample
Text preview

The term "instruction" can encompass various aspects of education, such as the act, process, or pursuit of educating or receiving education. Additionally, it can pertain to the specific subject or discipline taught in educational institutions that are dedicated to this act, process, or pursuit.

Instruction can come in different forms, such as formal or informal, private or public, and applicable to individual or societal contexts.

Nevertheless, it consistently entails the development of temperaments, abilities, accomplishments, cognitions, and beliefs.

There are certain methods for studying or reflecting upon attitudes, values, and character traits. Instruction subjects examine the activity or endeavor through questioning its purposes and methods.

Effects, signifiers, history, costs, value.

Both the procedure of instruction and the subject of instruction are encompassed within the doctrine of education. It can be regarded as a part of the subject since it relates to the purposes an

...

d relations to society.

The text discusses various aspects of education, including signifiers, methods, and consequences. It can also be viewed from a metadisciplinary perspective, focusing on constructs and purposes.

Even in the latter instance, metaphilosophy is considered a part of philosophy, just as methodology and techniques are considered parts of the subject.

Even though the concept of scientific discipline is not considered a part of science, historically, theories of education have typically been presented first. However, influenced by analytical philosophy, they have occasionally been presented second. In the initial form.

Traditionally, philosophers such as Aristotle, Augustine, and John Locke developed the doctrine of instruction as part of their philosophical systems and within the context of their ethical theories. However.

Instruction doctrine in the 20th century was primarily developed within schools of instruction, specifically within the context of foundations o

View entire sample
Join StudyHippo to see entire essay

instruction. As a result, it became associated with other areas of education such as educational history, psychological science, and sociology, rather than other aspects of doctrine.

The concept's development also included non-professional philosophers or those associated with formal schools of thought, such as Paul Goodman and Robert M. Hutchins. Given the various types of philosophy, there exist multiple belief systems.

There are numerous methods of philosophizing and countless forms of educational doctrine and approaches to creating it. Essentially, there is not one singular doctrine of instruction; instead, there are multiple doctrines classified in numerous ways. Thus, the term "doctrine of instruction" lacks a specific description.

The comparison and examination of different educational systems, whether from the past or present, is only concerned with tracing its own history. Any inquiries about this subject are left to the fields of history and sociology of education. Analytic philosophy of education is beyond the scope of education itself and does not attempt to propose definitive statements.

The text discusses instruction, which can be either factual or normative. It describes the approach to instruction as an analysis, aiming to define or clarify educational concepts such as learning and indoctrination.

The text discusses various aspects related to education, such as skills, traits, and the concept of instruction itself. It also mentions the analysis and criticism of educational mottos like "Teach kids, not subjects." All these elements are part of the task at hand.

Analytical philosophy utilizes logic and linguistics tools, as well as various analysis techniques employed by different philosophers. The outcomes of this approach can be appreciated for their intrinsic value, but they can also be beneficial to individuals seeking more evidence-based or ethical

decision-making in education, and who prioritize a cautious approach in reaching these decisions. This particular entry serves as an example of applying analytical philosophy in the field of education. Normative educational doctrines or theories can utilize the findings from analytical work and factual investigations concerning human beings and the psychology of learning.

However, in all cases, they put forward ideas about the nature of education, the values it should promote, the reasons for promoting them, and how it should achieve them in individuals.

Every case of educational enterprise implies a normative theory of instruction that dictates what forms it should take. Whether instruction is intentionally engaged in or not, it is assumed that certain temperaments are desirable and certain methods should be used to achieve or enhance them. Therefore, any stance on these matters represents a normative theory of doctrine of instruction. However, not all of these theories can be considered adequately philosophical.

There may be various types of individuals. Some individuals aim to promote the desired temperaments of a society using methods defined by its civilization.

In a more pluralistic society, both the terminals and the agencies of instruction are shaped by cultural tradition. Additionally, others also seek guidance from the prevailing civilization in nurturing desired temperaments, and perhaps even in selecting methods, including those derived from science.

An educational theory may emerge as a middle ground between opposing views on AIDS, especially in relation to instructional methods, especially in public schools.

Persons or groups within a society may have conflicting doctrines of instruction, but the public doctrine of instruction is a compromise between them. More comprehensive theories of instruction base their views on factual premises about humans and

their world and normative premises about what is good or right for individuals to pursue or achieve.

Advocates of these theories can establish their premises through either reasoning (including scientific discipline) and logic or through religion and divine authority. Both types of theories are referred to as educational doctrines. However, only those based on reasoning and logic are appropriately philosophical in nature; the others could be more appropriately labeled as divine doctrines of education. Even the purely philosophical ones can vary in complexity and enlightening qualities. In a comprehensive philosophical normative theory of education, analysis of the described types is also included.

The following types of propositions are typically present: additional decisions on instructional methods. For example, Aristotle argued that happiness is achieved through the Good and excellent activity; he also identified two types of excellent activity for individuals, one of which is rational (e.g.).

Making geometry and following lesson example (e.g., making mere actions) are both essential. Therefore, anyone capable of performing these activities should possess knowledge of geometry and a disposition to be fair. Acquiring knowledge of geometry necessitates instruction, while developing a sense of fairness requires practicing mere actions. It is crucial for the youth to receive instruction in geometry and practice making fair decisions.

Thus, in the beginning, philosophy can focus on education, resulting in the development of a proper philosophy of education and becoming part of the field of education.

Secondly, the general doctrine may be a subject in higher education. Additionally, the doctrine of education may also be included as a part of teacher training curriculum. This is important for instructors to think critically and thoroughly about their work. Lastly, it is presumed that

doctrine of instruction should be integrated into the course of study for teachers.

In a society where there is an individual system of instruction governed by a prevailing theory of instruction, a philosopher can take on one of four roles regarding instruction. First, they can analyze the concepts and reasoning associated with instruction in order to make people's thinking about it as clear, explicit, and logical as possible. Second, they can support the prevailing system by providing philosophical arguments in favor of the desired temperaments and methods. Third, they can criticize the system and attempt to reform it based on a different philosophical theory of instruction they have developed. Or fourth, they can simply teach logic and philosophy to future educators and parents with the hope that they will apply these principles to educational affairs.

In a pluralistic society like the United States, where a significant portion of the educational system relies on finding common ground between conflicting viewpoints, philosophers have the opportunity to create various things. They can create any of the things previously mentioned. In the first half of the 20th century, professional philosophers in the United States mostly focused on creating the latter mentioned things. However, by the end of the 20th century, they started striving to create more diverse creations.

Indeed, there will be more opportunities for these activities in a diverse society, as debates about education will always exist or possibly be resumed. A philosopher could also play a significant role in explaining and improving a balanced theory of education. Furthermore, they may not just be an eclectic thinker, but rather something more.

The author proposes that the support for the via media

program can be justified based on a comprehensive societal doctrine. Specifically, the author suggests that a complete public doctrine should be introduced for public school education, clearly outlining the attitudes it should strive to promote and the methods it should use to promote them.

And which ones should be left for the place, the church, and other private agencies of instruction to cultivate. In any instance, he might recommend appealing to scientific enquiry and experiment whenever possible. A philosopher may also work out a fully developed educational doctrine of his own and start an experimental school in which to put it into practice.

Just like John Dewey, this person may advocate excessively for society to fully embrace his ideas. He might even try to persuade others about the benefits of promoting specific temperaments through specific methods.

Partially based on experience and scientific discipline, and partially based on premises from other areas of his philosophy - including ethics, value theory, political and social doctrine, and epistemology and metaphysics.

In a pluralistic society, philosophers should take into account different beliefs and teachings, such as the concept of head or doctrine, to better understand various ideas and perspectives. By doing this, they can support educators who prioritize moral values.

By displaying scientific, historical, aesthetic, or spiritual instruction, they offer a diverse range of knowledge.

With a doctrine of morality, scientific discipline, history, and art, severally.

The individual has the ability to contemplate and discuss education, delving into its nature as a subject, its specific content, and the various approaches used in the field of philosophy of education. Additionally, people have the freedom to shape their goals and methodologies based on personal beliefs or religious convictions.

The

philosopher of scientific discipline would be involved in the instruction of scientific disciplines, considering whether it qualifies as a scientific discipline. This is exemplified by the case of Marx.

Plato attempted to provide the political ideology that drove the revolution in Syracuse, while the philosophes accomplished a similar feat for France in the 18th century. This kind of endeavor can be undertaken anywhere, as numerous individuals urge schools to construct a fresh societal framework.

According to Dewey, instruction is the process of organizing basic characteristics in relation to nature and other human beings. He believed that doctrine can be considered as the most comprehensive theory of instruction. In this sense, doctrine encompasses divinity, poetry, and philosophy, guiding us on what to believe and how to perceive humanity and the world.

While it is not necessarily true, this statement could be referring to philosophy in a narrow sense or suggesting that all philosophy is instructive, aiming to provide guidance. However, this is not the sole purpose of classical philosophy or even of philosophy as reconstructed by Dewey. Classical philosophy aimed for truth rather than simply following a set of instructions.

and the latter has other practical terminals besides that of steering the educational endeavor. Surely, analytical doctrine has other terminals. However, although Dewey did not have analytical doctrine in mind.

However, analytical doctrine can also be considered the most general theory of instruction. It does not prescribe specific temperaments to be formed, but it does analyze and criticize the concepts, statements, and methods used in any study or reflection on education.

This text discusses a collection of essays written by professional philosophers that are not focused on the topic of the doctrine

of instruction. The philosophers do not reference any works within this subject, as they are confident about their understanding of it. They do not hesitate to speak authoritatively about what doctrine has to say to pedagogues. However, it may be worth considering a more self-critical approach to the doctrine of instruction, even if it sometimes feels like examining its own foundations.

Considering the potential for productivity, believing about instruction is influenced by a tendency towards self-criticism. This supports keeping important questions alive and open for further examination. When writing an encyclopedia article, it is necessary to take a stance on differing perspectives. Despite striving for neutrality and inclusivity in describing a field, it is impossible to avoid making some kind of statement in the process.

Claims that dispute would be set upon are those, especially the "categorical" attacks, which revolve around a list of types of instructional doctrine.

Regardless of distinct schools of thought or specific disciplinary methods, the field has experienced a period of peculiar diverseness and interdisciplinarity that has continued into the 21st century. However, such portrayals may seem artificial and even worse than that, potentially imperial and exclusionary.

The challenge is to find a way to accurately assess the field while also considering the impact of word pictures, including its own impact. This must be done within the context of evolving disciplinary boundaries and methods, which are constantly undergoing debate. Additionally, these urges overlap and interact with different approaches that may initially seem unrelated. These urges coexist within broader philosophical movements.

Even within the idea of single philosophers themselves, there can be conflicting viewpoints that help explain the inclination towards automatic introspection and uncertainty in the

field of philosophy of education. This inclination is the oldest and most enduring disposition, focused on offering a philosophically supported concept of what learning's purposes and activities should be. Plato's Republic serves as an example of this.

The prescriptions mentioned in this text come from different sources. Some of them are derived from a utopian vision, while others come from detailed reconceptions of the daily activities of learning, such as John Locke's Some Thoughts Concerning Education or Rousseau's Emile. There are also prescriptions that are derived from societal or moral rules, like various Kantian positions of instruction (despite Immanuel Kant having little to say on the topic himself).

These normative dispositions encompass various aspects of what individuals anticipate from the doctrine of instruction: a more enlightened stance, a more comprehensive societal outlook, and a perception of motivation and loftier purposes. This is essentially what people typically refer to when discussing the concept of having a "philosophy of instruction."

There is a variety of positions in the field that share this desire for a standard way of thinking. These positions can be classified under what was once referred to as the "isms" approach (perennialism, idealism, pragmatism, Thomism, etc.) which holds the belief that a set of philosophical principles can generate a thorough and cohesive educational strategy.

For a long time, the focus of the field was on understanding the specifics of these "philosophies of education." The debates among the different "isms" were often rooted in fundamental philosophical differences. As a result, disagreements were typically categorical, with no middle ground.

The text discusses the amalgamation of realist and idealist worldviews. A clever individual has proposed that the traditional "isms" have recently been

substituted by the contemporary "ists," which are less purely philosophical and more concerned with social and political theories. These theories are commonly embraced by scholars in the field of educational philosophy, such as Marxists, feminists, multiculturalists, and postmodernists.

Below, the text will discuss doctrines that are characterized as critically oriented. However, it is important to note that these views can also be driven by normative beliefs. For example, authors such as neo-Marxist advocates of Paulo Freire's "critical pedagogy" provide explicit explanations of how education should proceed, its purpose, and whose interests it should serve.

The Analytical Impulse is the second urge that motivates much of the doctrine of instruction. It encompasses not only philosophical approaches referred to as "analytical philosophy" (such as conceptual analysis or ordinary language analysis), but also a broader perspective that sees the philosophical task as defining a set of rational criteria that educational goals and practices should meet. However, it leaves it to other public deliberative processes to determine these specific criteria. In this expanded sense.

The analytical urge can be observed not only in analytical doctrine itself, but also in studies focusing on logical and epistemic criteria of critical thinking, as well as the identification of informal fallacies in reasoning. It can be found in certain types of broad theory that establish general principles of rights and justice, while remaining silent on specific educational objectives. Furthermore, it can be found in certain versions of Jurgen Habermas's theory, which proposes a framework for communicative deliberation that must satisfy a set of "validity" claims without pre-determining the outcome of the deliberative process. The analytical urge is often viewed as a form of philosophical modesty, wherein

philosophers do not dictate educational choices to others, but rather aim to clarify the rational procedures by which these choices should be made.

The concept of philosophy of education is often metaphorized as referees who try to impartially judge an ongoing activity or groundsmen who tend to the weeds and dirt without deciding what to plant. These metaphors influence how this version of philosophy of education is presented and justified to others. The idea that philosophy provides a set of tools and that actively engaging in philosophy of education offers a more practical self-perception of the philosopher opposes the notion of philosophy as a system-building endeavor.

It should be noted that this impulse is not completely without the normative inclination. Additionally, there is a prescription regarding the actual tools and standards.

The text highlights the presence of rules and analytical differentiations in job framing, which are often seen as educational ideals aimed at promoting critical thinking and Habermasian communication in the classroom. While these arguments may be logically justified, some individuals may perceive them as imposed from a higher authority.

Furthermore, at a more profound level, the distinction between analytic and prescriptive becomes less clear: a theory of logic or a theory of communication, while still strictly procedural, aims to be.

The text highlights how human nature, society, cognition, and linguistic communication are intertwined and contain societal and cultural elements that may appear "natural" or "neutral" to those who support these processes.

However, others may perceive this as being foreign and specific to one's own beliefs. It is not intended as a criticism of the analytical orientation, but rather demonstrates how these desires can coexist. This is true even in accounts

that identify themselves as primarily one or the other. The Critical Impulse shares a similar inclination.

Both a critical orientation and an analytical one can coexist, as they both seek to clear up misconceptions and political orientations that hinder the needs and interests of marginalized groups. This critical urge is similar to the normative urge.

The critical urge is fueled by a vision of an improved, fairer, and more just society. What sets the critical urge apart from others is its recognition of the role that doctrine can play in achieving these goals.

Doctrine is not just a collection of tools or an abstract programmatic theory; it is a significant personal and political commitment. It stems from deeper attitudes towards protecting and serving the interests of particular groups. As a result, critically oriented doctrines of instruction emphasize key philosophical ideas such as reflection, counterhegemony, and a critique of power.

The text highlights that various critical theories (such as those emphasizing difference) derive their power from their ability to challenge a presumed oppressive dominant society. They enable exploited individuals and groups to acknowledge and challenge their circumstances and be motivated to bring about change. While there are normative and analytical aspects in critical theories of education, other philosophies of education can also have critical elements. Philosophers of education driven by normative or analytical motivations can share many of the same social and political commitments as critical philosophers of education. Some may even view their work as ultimately serving the same goals of criticizing dominant ideologies and promoting human liberation.

The importance of not categorizing these three urges or orientations simply as classes for specific doctrines or philosophers cannot be

overlooked. Recognizing them as urges emphasizes the motivational qualities that underlie and often propel the adoption of certain philosophical positions. Although philosophers tend to emphasize the power of argumentation in influencing their acceptance of such positions.

At a surface level, philosophers are influenced by statements and reasons which make them change their opinions. However, on a deeper level, they are unlikely to alter the underlying motives that drive their philosophical inquiries. By highlighting the possibility of all three urges coexisting in various philosophical ideologies and individual philosophers, it becomes evident that these influences persist.

The history of philosophy underscores the intricate and even conflicting nature of the philosophical mindset. When philosophers teach or discuss their beliefs, they certainly present statements, references to literature, and other forms of evidence. However, on a deeper level, they are appealing to a common desire within their audience.

One aspect that is more difficult to comprehend directly and without which the statements themselves are unlikely to be understood is the deductions of the Impulses for Philosophy of Education. Considering the existence of these three urges, how can they contribute to providing an overview of the field of doctrine of education that does not rely on statements about disciplinary boundary maintenance? Firstly, these broad orientations are, in many ways, easier to generalize within the field compared to any specific set of disciplinary standards. Various forms of doctrine of education can exhibit these types of dispositions.

Indeed, it is quite remarkable how people with drastically different paradigms can be motivated by similar underlying philosophical commitments. Recognizing this fact might encourage them to engage in respectful discourse despite their differences. Additionally, philosophers should realize that

the validity they ascribe to certain statements may not solely be influenced by their objective significance.

However, other than through a unique request, these types of statements have a certain appeal. This type of reflection can have various benefits, but one significant advantage is that it can enhance a person's understanding of why others may not be convinced by statements that seem obvious to them. It also provides insight into why the power of argument alone may not be enough to generate philosophical understanding or resolve disagreement. Considering the pervasive and interdisciplinary nature of the field of philosophy of education, fostering a spirit of tolerance and inclusiveness is important.

Although not requiring to be unlimited entirely, it would be a valuable remedy to the historical tendency to establish the methods or the philosophical school that separates the true doctrine of education from the impostors. Supporters of more normative approaches typically support their argument for dominance by referring to canonical Great Works such as Plato, ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle, and Locke.

Rousseau and Dewey both engage in this type of system-building that spans across epistemic, ethical, and social/political matters, which is characteristic of great philosophers.

It is becoming clear that for them, the study of doctrine of instruction was rarely seen as an independent field of investigation. Instead, it was considered to be the practical application of knowledge.

Get an explanation on any task
Get unstuck with the help of our AI assistant in seconds
New