Law is manifestly a plurality of pluralities Essay Example
Law is manifestly a plurality of pluralities Essay Example

Law is manifestly a plurality of pluralities Essay Example

Available Only on StudyHippo
  • Pages: 12 (3209 words)
  • Published: February 15, 2018
  • Type: Article
View Entire Sample
Text preview

Fuzziness is often contested as disingenuous and meaningless in various postmodern topics, but this is not at all the case in legal field; though addressing the limitations of current law theories is prerequisite, the pluralist approach to law attempts to diagnose conflicts between the overlapping pluralities of social and legal fields; to recognize it's fuzziness, in order to find practical solutions to deal with such fuzzy situations, as Melissa (2004: 76 in Menses 2006: 5) stated: The study of the legal must be directed towards the discovery of alternative receptions of the world and Justice and of different practices of solving practical problems by accommodating competing interests as well as meeting the prerequisites of substantive Justice. The question of law and justice then becomes one concerning our whole way of life, how we perceive and place ourselves in our surroundings.

Menses

...

addresses the essential need for awareness of pluralistic effects from globalization, or 'globalization' (Robertson 1995), and that legal scholars should search for pluralistic deflation for law, and to acquire a holistic view on law and justice In a global sense, in order to see the real bigger picture. As Menses (2006: 5) describes: Global migration patterns, old and new, and multiple exchanges between different states, economies, societies and legal systems, on a variety of scales and through different methods, have over time created transnational, Inherently plural, multi- ethnic and multicultural legal environments, which are becoming ever more prominent in reality today.

The paradigm shift of globalization continuously Increases the interconnectedness of individuals; the effects of globalization is a conspicuous fact.

Yet, it's critical relevancy to legal field has not yet sufficiently recognizes b

View entire sample
Join StudyHippo to see entire essay

legal scholars due to the nomination of resurrection positivism for more than two hundred years. While in other cases. New natural law theorists tend to hold a unrealistic assumption of global uniformity as the key to harmony. On the surface, the two approaches both seem very definite, ideal, 'UN-fuzzy; the internal pluralistic nature of these theories will be discussed later; neither theory is ever close enough to adequately solve fuzzy problems In the Indispensable social dimensions of law.

Once a law student Like myself becomes plurality-conscious, it becomes obvious and imperative that one would circumspectly study all major theoretical approaches to law that have been presented throughout human history from major parts of the world, in this essay for example, the development of Vivid and Hindu law shall be discussed to demonstrate the oldest plurality-conscious state; only by researching through a variety of content- specific lens will allow us to look deeper into subjects of law objectively (Twining analyses the interaction between major theoretical approaches, and lastly attempt to demonstrate the overlapping relationship between 'pop' elements in law by bringing in Mink's conceptual kite model before my conclusion.

The history of natural law is a tale of search of mankind for absolute Justice and of its failure' (Friedman, 1967; 95) Natural law theorists maintain that the human race is blessed to be born with innate conscience, the ability to reason, moral from immoral, right form wrong; again quoting Friedman's explanation of Aristotle view that became the foundation of Stoic's contribution to natural law theory (1947:22 in Menses 137): Man is part of nature in a twofold sense; on the one hand he is part

of matter, part of the creatures of God; as such he partakes of experience; but man is also endowed tit active reason which distinguishes him from all other parts of nature. As such he is capable of forming his will in accordance with the insight of his reason. From a natural law point of view, rules are manifested through a universal code of moral principles for all human submit to.

Only few absolute natural law can be drawn from holy scriptures, it was not enough to provide regulations on issues concerning family, slavery, property or government during Roman period, nevertheless those subjects were to stay in society due to 'deterioration of mankind' (Friedman, 1967: 101 in Menses 2006: 138).

To handle this situation, Christianizes Romans cleverly gave rise to 'relative' natural law that would eventually proceed to 'legislation guided by reason, which should conform as closely as possible to absolute natural law' (Menses 2006: 139) Undoubtedly, proposing the sinful man fallen from grace as an excuse to allow human law-making, certainly seemed contradicting, and threatening to compromise, the original ideal principles of the absolute Law of Nature; The current stage of discussion is revealing the transition of early Christianizes Western state from basing natural law theory as the foundation of it's legal philosophy, to eventually heavily adopting legal positivism in principle of law making.

This occurrence prompted one of the earliest legal pluralist view in the Western world, theorized by SST Thomas Aquinas (1226-74), affirming the internal pluralistic nature in natural law, as explained by Harris (1980: 8 in Menses 2006: 142): His legal theory encompasses four types of law. 'Eternal law comprises God-given rules

governing all creation. 'Natural law' is that segment of eternal law which is discoverable through the special process of reasoning mapped out by the pagan authors-intuitions of the natural deductions drawn therefore. 'Divine law' has been revealed in Scripture.

'Human law' consists of rules, supportable by reason, but articulated by human authorities for the common good. As to the interrelation between these different types of law, two crucial propositions stand out in Thomas philosophy. First, human law derive their legal quality, their power to bind in conscience, from natural law..

.

In some instances, the content of law is deductible from first principles of natural law; for the rest, the legislator has the freedom of an s a mere corruption of law and so not binding by virtue of its own legal quality; nevertheless, even if an enactment is contrary to natural law and so 'unjust', obedience may still be proper to avoid bad example or civil disturbance. Aquinas' approach already suggested legal pluralism through his 'understanding that different types of law co-exist and interact with each other harmoniously and conflictingly (Menses 2006: 142) His theories in fact endorse legal positivism, deeming it acceptable as long as human-law makers or rulers maintain their reasoning and values obsequious to religion (Menses 2006: 143); As Christianizes Europe adopted

Aquinas theories, it led to later ascendancy of legal positivism; this cause and effect is easy to comprehend from Liberation's (1971 : 23) analysis on the relationship between natural law and positive law: Since positive law is based on the law of nature, its contents must be in harmony with this law. But the lawgiver has got the right to

supplement the law of nature in many ways according to the needs of the particular society.

The right of property, for instance, has been introduced by positive law. This is also the case with punishments. The precepts of the law of nature are not devoid of sanctions; their inactions are the pangs of conscience. But human punishments are a human invention, though the Justification of punishment rests on the law of nature.

The law of nature, therefore, gives wide scope to the activity of the sovereign as lawgiver. But he cannot do anything contrary to the law of nature. If he did so, his precepts would lack binding force; they might create fear, but they could not impose obligations. Base on this reasoning, formal laws, are merely meant to formalize the moral principles humans ourselves already recognize.

To summarize natural law theory, it has three sources of moral authority to support it's law making approach. Firstly points to religion sources such as holy books, scriptures. Second, intellectual origin, which is emphasizes by John Stuart Mill's 'harm principle'.

Third, being the natural origin, proposed by Aquinas that there are certain laws in nature, and that everything else derives from there; whether or not a moral code will be successful, it depends on if there is enough people ascribe to that moral code; When we look at all the human flows, migration, travel, tourism, is it possible to find a homogeneous group in our glossing world? If not, how do we determine which particular morality is going o be imposed on everyone? These questions have been imprudently neglected by resurrection legal theorists; morality is subjective, different individuals

have contradicting culture-specific views on what's right and wrong, questions like whether marijuana should be illegal, or whether homosexuality should be tolerated, simply cannot be satisfyingly answered by natural law theory due to it's lack for recognition for pluralities in our society.

According to the Positivist tradition, a law or 'norm' has the status of law if a recognizes human authority declares it to be law (Kelsey 1999: 9 in Menses 2006: deity. The content of the law, such as morality, from a positivist perspective is irrelevant; this legal approach only concerns whether or not the law is enacted by a sovereignty. For a law to be valid in the positivist tradition, a law must have the correct pedigree, referring to the established procedure for law making that must be followed by the sovereignty. The positivists assess the validity of law by asking whether the law is created by the correct authority and whether the correct authority followed the appropriate procedures (Menses 2006: 152).

A law is valid only if the answers are yes to both questions. Criticism points to positivism's failure to Justify the process by which a law is enact. Imagine as a positivist being asked: how to determine whether the rule that allows the last Parliament to make law, is itself valid? We are stuck! We cannot logically determine the validity of the rule that Parliament decrees our law, by asking whether Parliament decreed, that it decrees our law; it makes no sense! This scenario demonstrates the great positivist fallacy as Menses points Dutton 2006: 153) If law is simply law because it is said by someone in authority to be law

(Morrison, 1997: 1), we face a dangerous circularity problem.

So positivists like Hart, or Kelsey, attempted to provide some escape to this conundrum; Hart added that the rule governs law making is 'socially accepted' (Menses 2006: 1 55) When the rule that governs the creation of law is rejected, example situations such as protest, civil disobedience, revolutions, these social rejections invalidate the law-making procedure, and invalidate the laws themselves.

Kelsey suggests that the rules that authorize the sovereign to make law exists in what he refers to the the 'Groundnut'; it is a fundamental norm, upon which all other norm, and thus, all other laws will rest. Menses (2006: 158) made such observation of Skeleton's theory: asserting that in every legal system a hierarchy of norms is traceable to the most basic of norms.

Kelsey accepted that such a norm could take different forms, and even acknowledged that there could be more than one Groundnut Kelsey clearly recognizes pluralistic multi-layers of overlapping norms, the keyword 'Groundnut' was formulated throughout Shekel's quest for 'pure theory, from such quest of 'pureness' he succeeded theorizing his model independent of any other legal norm, at the same time refused to include the inalienable social-cultural aspect which the basic norm must ultimately dependent on, conveniently avoid tainting his 'pure theory of law with 'legal pluralism'. 'Soft positivist" Hart (1961) proposed a distinction between 'primary rules' and 'secondary rules'; where the former imposes obligation and the later confer powers, although implies apparent legal plurality in his dual model, Menses contests(2006: 1 59) that Hart's theory remains 'insufficiently concerned about socio-cultural legal facts to become deeply incorporated as a separate entity into

a plurality-conscious, globosity-focused analysis. ' regarding status of wealth, gender, ethnicity..

. C In many instances, these differences will lead to conflict. Socio-legal experts addresses the myth that the state does not take sides in these conflicts, where system is neutral and treats everyone equally, fairly and Justly. Socio-legal experts argues that legal order is in fact a self- serving system (Menses 2006: 166). This position is very different from the position that one has seen in natural law and legal positivism which suggests universal acceptance and agreement on what laws should be.

In reality, there is no agreement but conflicts, we all live in states where certain powerful groups within society imposing their will upon everyone else (Menses 2006: 164).

Pound assumes(Menses: 165) a value-consensus model of social relations, where groups may disagree or conflict, but there should be general agreement surrounding the law and the ability of the legal system to resolve things in a neutral manner, the assumption is that stability is the norm; others proposed a value antagonism model which rejects Pounds claim of consensus; explaining riots, revolutions or civil wars don't happen more often is because powerful groups are able to access state power to prevent weaker groups from causing trouble (Freeman 2001: 676 in Menses 2006: 165). Legal realist see Judiciary decision making as a subjective exercise, thus produce ambiguous, inconsistent, often contradicting results. This can be observed through majority decisions: rulings such as three to two, the numbers vary; how is that possible? All of these Judges are looking at the same facts, applying the same law, presumably they're drawing from the same precedents, and yet they are reaching

different conclusion due to subjectivity.

Scandinavian realists such as Axel Hygrometers (1868-1939) denied the existence of objective values, as Dais and Hughes scribed (1957: 482 Menses 2006: 166): This leads Hygrometers to deny the possibility of any science of the Ought.

All questions of Justice, aims, purposes and the reality of law are matters of personal evaluation and not susceptible to any scientific processes of examination. In this way many of the traditional problems of legal philosophy become illusory, and must replaced by an examination of the actual use of legal terms and concepts and a psychological analysis of the mental attitudes that are involved. What influence the outcome of the case is not merely the facts or the law, but rather he Judges, therefore one should take their moral, their beliefs, their particular position within society, their upbringing, their schooling into account.

The writings of Karl Liberation also made a direct challenge to positivism, stating that the outcome of legal dispute is determined by Judge's morality, mood, personality (Messes 2006: 167) Alfa Ross maintain that Judges can interpret the law, thus Judges should be motivated by the public good. (Menses 2006: 168) Legal realists are certainly plurality- conscious scholars by emphasizing the social dimensions of legal development. In he recent socio-legal scholarship, researchers remain overly focused on specific narrow agenda and not enough emphasis on globosity-focused Jurisprudence (Menses 2006: 168) .

the traditional recognition of a divine cosmic force as a guide to law-making.

They seek to accentuate individual rights and duties, while appreciating the pluralities in defining 'goodness'; What is 'good' depends ultimately to a large extent on social construction and considerations of

situation-specificity and it may not matter whether it is legal or not. ' (Menses 2006: 171) Global legal uniformity is seemingly unrealistic as we gradually realist the nature of libations is indeed a pluralistic phenomenon; many globalization manifested in different places, which brings about the more accurate term 'globalization' coined by Robertson (1995, in Menses, 2006: 4). Such observation confirms the rising of interdependence and interrelatedness of cultures and societies.

In time like this, a plurality-focused perspective is essential to comprehend the enormous conceptual complexities of the term 'law' (Menses 2006: 173) Manikin's conceptual kite model presents the interlinked plurality nature of law in a sensible visual manner, including efferent competing concepts of law on each corner, while the emphasis of importance may shift from one corner to another, depends on the specificity, none of these four elements should be ignored when handling law; in the following discussion, Manikin's kite model is borrowed to illustrate the 'pop' elements throughout the development of traditional Hindu law and their dynamic interactions. Figure 1 . Kite Model Corner 1: Natural Law Theory (Religions, ethics, values) Corner 2: Socio-legal Theory (Society) Corner 3: Legal Positivism (State) Corner 4: New Natural Law (Globalization, human rights)

Kite: Legal pluralism (all corners are interlinked and interdependent, Law is a dynamic compound entity) Source: Menses (201 AAA) Traditional Hindu law is founded upon its plurality-conscious sophistication from [A]t least four interlinked stages of conceptual development within traditional' Hindu law itself, from the microcosmic universal Order (rite) of the Vivid system to the microcosmic self-controlled order (dharma) of classical Hindu law proper, and the deterrence-based stage of punishment (Danna) and more or less formal

dispute processing (Aviva?RA) in the late classical and post-classical system. Prior to traditional Hindu law, Vivid period (c.

1500 BC to c. 00 BC) gave rise to the term rite corresponds to the microcosmic Order With a big O' (Menses AAA: 17), which signifies Vivid people's understanding of the interrelatedness of all things; such notion can be observed through Veda rituals where they describe a complex system of unknown sources, with intrinsic rules that are unknown to human; Stay, also a Sanskrit term parallel to rite, represents the secular dimensions of the natural order, signifying a definition of vision of Truth. Such view of natural order is also parallel to Greek legal philosophy of theme's, which highlights the relationship between divine power and human actions (Menses, 2006: 134-7) These Vivid concepts remain fundamentally relevant to later emergence of the concept dharma during classical period of Hindu law (c. 500 BC to c. 200 AD) which translates to 'good action' (Menses, 2006: 209). Such concept is clearly more socially focused rather than state-power focused, thus also carry pluralistic meaning open to different interpretations.

Harm and its dynamic pluralistic nature derived from four different sources, titanium's (individual ethics), sidecars (good' customs), Marti (remembered truth) and shrubs (heard knowledge/Veda); these sources delineate the development of early Hindu law, from a microcosmic realization of higher Order, corresponding to top corner of natural law theory; to microcosmic duties of self-controlled order, drawing parallel to today's socio-legal approach from second corner of the kite. (Menses 2006: 209) Hindus early ideal assumption of individuals acting accordingly base solely on the concept of dharma soon confronted challenges. The notions of Danna and Aviva?RA

were developed during the late classical period, present themselves as necessary gal refinement for such self-controlled order (Menses 2006: 210).

These notions further demonstrate Hindu people's gradual comprehension of the pluralistic nature of law regulations; applications of such terms can simultaneously overlapping within individuals mind, community, or through dispute settlement and formal punishment which invite state's power to intervene; regarding the shift towards corner 3 of the kite Menses (2006: 225) notes: [l]t is still not the state which determines the rules of human coexistence in traditional Hindu law; the primary rules are still a cosmic given with local flavors. This again confirms the superiority of the 'pop' entities rite and dharma, being the foundation principle of self-regulation.

The use of Hart's term 'primary rules' points to served as a public agent, to assist the 'secondary rules' such as Aviva?RA, for the sake of higher Order; far from being considered as central determination of legal rules. In spite of the rise of Overenthusiastic, questions about dharma are mainly negotiated and settled through local customs, holding rite to its overarching role. Late classical Hindu law, unlike the Europeans, avoided domination of legal activism. The use of conceptual kite model (Menses, 2006) to address different elements within the historical development of traditional Hindu law exemplifies that all major legal theories are indeed interconnected and continuously interdependent due to the culture-specificity of law. Not one single theoretical approach is enough to provide an adequate comprehension of the intrinsic plurality nature of law.

Get an explanation on any task
Get unstuck with the help of our AI assistant in seconds
New